I do apologize for the lateness of this blog post. Around my
usual working time on Monday I was attending an academic conference concerning
theories and best practices within the field of higher education
administration, and specifically experiential learning. Although I do value
this work very much, I couldn’t pass up the opportunity to be the only
undergraduate student amongst 100+ professionals!
I’ve bit the bullet of what we have comically named the “St.
Dewey” attitude and decided to look into the work of Thomas D. Fallace.
Specifically I am looking at Was John
Dewey Ethnocentric? Reevaluating the Philosopher’s Early Views on Culture and
Race. While I do admit that Fallace argues well, and that his points do coincide
with his title well, I believe that they do not hold much water concerning our
studies.
The first point that stands out to me is Fallace’s careful
wording. As he states, [o]verall, I
provide a nuanced, contextualized reading of Dewey’s views on culture and race
during a critical period of his intellectual development (1895-1911) (471). Surely
it is important to note that this is before Dewey’s revealing trip to China,
and before the revision of How We Think.
Fallace argues that the primary texts of Dewey’s philosophy that are used for
education are taken from this early period, however. But is this a proper
consideration, to avoid the later works of Dewey and simply focus on these
earlier views?
“To study a philosopher” is truly an ambiguous statement.
What are you studying? A living or dead body? Accounts of this philosopher
written by other people? The writings of this philosopher? Who was this
philosopher in the first place? A person, or a series of writings? Their past,
or what they had become? Such questions of being are pointed out in Sartre’s
existentialism. His philosophy is a bit off topic, but I will throw it into sum
by stating that Sartre points out the paradox of human existence in that we are
what we have been and something completely different at the same time. If I
have been a waiter and I am waiting tables now, surely I am a waiter, but at
the same time I am not a waiter since I have the innate freedom to be anything
I wish to be. So if I am ethnocentric now, and yet I choose to purport myself
in the future as not ethnocentric, am I still ethnocentric due to what I had
argued in the past? If this waiter chooses to manage his own restaurant, or
become a NASCAR driver, is he still a waiter?
In other words, it is confusing and illusory to throw human
existence into something definite, for we are not definite. The entire idea of
humanity is that a human being is constantly becoming something. To say “Dewey
was ethnocentric” in general is to argue Dewey as some sort of object. Fallace’s
careful choice to focus on specific writings of Dewey evades this paradox, but
runs into another problem rather quickly.
What are these earlier views that Fallace points out? Dewey did not specifically address (472) views
on race and culture during this time. Fallace points towards the verbiage of
Dewey, indicating that such terminology is indicative of his views. To what
degree can this be said to be true? Fallace alludes to the writing of historian
Thomas Kuhn. [L]ook first for the
apparent absurdities in the text and ask yourself how a sensible person could
have written them (xiii). I
believe that Fallace hits the wall with this quote. In looking for these
absurdities that change the meaning of these texts, who is looking? Surely it
is Fallace. How can this be said to be a fair presumption of absurdity? In
trying to decipher the work of Dewey there is a profound culture gap. To regard
these terms, savage, barbarian,
primitive, as intellectually absurd and denotive of ethnocentric behavior
requires a first-hand understanding of American intellectual culture at the
time, modes of communication and acceptable terms. These words are indeed taboo
in contemporary American culture, but surely they are not within Dewey’s
culture. To label him as ethnocentric based on these assumptions gives
ill-consideration to the situation. Labeling terms have been used throughout
mankind (falling back to Sartre’s philosophy, terms that try to define
humanity, which is indefinable by nature since it is always becoming). These
terms help us to create the illusion of organization within our chaotic and
insensible world. Every so often, these words are subscribed with hate within a
culture, deemed as taboo, and done away with. Let us think to ourselves how
often this happens and wonder how long it will be until words such as gay or lesbian receive this taboo. What is to become of the psychological academic
writings that have used these words to describe these people? Shall we cast
them into flames for using terms commonly accepted amongst society not to hate
others but to identify them?
The second point Fallace makes within the methodology of his
claims is that Dewey’s acceptance of this language and unvoiced opinions
concerning culture and race reflect his statement of habitudes which lie below the level of reflection. Are race and
culture included within these habitudes? I will admit that it is hard for me to
find evidence against this point. I am inclined to believe that Dewey is not
considering race and culture in this statement, but Fallace draws a painstaking
connection that perhaps Dewey believes that words like savage are below the level of
reflection.
I intend to look further into this piece and decide how well Fallace argues against the point I have brought up concerning the relevance of verbiage to the viewpoints of a person, and whether or not it is right to consider this philosophy (as a whole) as ethnocentric based on its early stages which had much influence on it, according to Fallace.
Fallace, T. (2010). Was John Dewey Ethnocentric?
Reevaluating the Philosopher’s Early Views on Culture and Race. Educational Researcher, Vol 39. No 6.
471-474
No comments:
Post a Comment